Monday, 15 June 2015

Philosophy of history 07-17-74-01-88







TABLE OF CONTENT



INTRODUCTION
·         Meaning of philosophy of History
·         Historical background of Georg Wilhelm Friendrich Hegel
·         Methods of writing History
MAIN BODY
·         Summarization of philosophy of History by Georg Wilhelm Friendrich Hegel
CONCLUSION


REFERENCES








Philosophy of history, is the study either of the historical process and its development or of the methods used by historians to understand their material.The term history may be employed in two quite different senses, it may mean  the events and actions that together make up the human past, or it may mean the accounts given of that past and the modes of investigation whereby they are arrived at or constructed[1]. When used in the first sense, the word refers to what as a matter of fact happened, while when used in the second sense it refers to the study and description of those happenings.
The notion of philosophical reflection upon history and its nature is consequently open to more than one interpretation, and modern writers have found it convenient to regard it as covering two main types of undertaking. On the one hand, they have distinguished philosophy of history in the traditional or classical sense; this is conceived to be a first-order enquiry, its subject matter being the historical process as a whole and its aim being, broadly speaking, one of providing an overall elucidation or explanation of the course and direction taken by that process. On the other hand, they have distinguished philosophy of history considered as a second-order enquiry. Here attention is focused not upon the actual sequence of events themselves but, instead, upon the procedures and categories used by practicing historians in approaching and comprehending their material[2]. The former, often alluded to as speculative philosophy of history, has had a long and varied career; the latter, which is generally known as critical or analytical philosophy of history, did not rise to prominence until the 20th century.
Hegel’s lectures on the philosophy of history are recognized in German as a popular introduction to his system; their form is less rigid than generality treatises and the illustrations, which occupy a large proportion of the work, are trains. Hegel argue that there are three methods of writing History and he distinguishing these three methods or modes of doing history as, Original History,
Firstly,Hegel argue that, Original history consists of an account of actions, events, and situations lived through and witnessed  by the historian. Other primary sources are used, but as "ingredients only",the account depends fundamentally on the historian's own witnessing of the times. Hegel cites Thucydides and Herodotus as examples. He also describes this type of recorded history as "history whose spirit (the historian) shared in," and notes that the primary task of "original history" is to create an internal, "mental representation" of external events. Original history must deal instead with the "observed and observable reality" of a people who are self aware and unique.
Further, original history cannot be of great external scope, it is a limited viewpoint, a portrait of the time. The original historian does not offer a great deal of theory about or reflection on the events and situations he or she recounts--"he lives within the spirit of the times and cannot as yet transcend them." For Hegel, the spirit in which the original historian is writing is the same as the spirit of the times he or she is writing about: "the spirit of the author and of the actions he tells of, are one and the same."[3]
Reflective History, This is the second historical method Hegel mentions. Reflective history is written after the time covered in the history has passed, and therefore it involves a remove at which the historian can analyze and interpret the events he covers. Reflective history is divided into four sub-methods: universal history, pragmatic, critical, and specialized.
Universal History, This is the first form of reflective history that Hegel sets out. Universal history seeks to provide an account of the whole history of a people, or even of the world. Unlike original history, the spirit in which a universal history is written is not the spirit of the times written about.[4] Since the extremely broad scope of universal history necessitates the intense compression of complex events into simple statements, the primary factor in such histories is the "thought" of the historian as he works to give a coherent, universal account.
Pragmatic History, Pragmatic history, the second type of reflective history, involves an ideology or interpretive method on the part of the historian, who uses historical events to back up a pointed argument. Hegel disdains pragmatic histories that seek to provide "moral lessons”
Critical History, This third type of reflective history seeks to re-interpret existing historical accounts. Critical history is a kind of history of history, which tests the accuracy of given accounts and perhaps poses alternative accounts.[5] Hegel dislikes this kind of history, which "extorts" new things to say from existing accounts. He points out that this is a cheaper way to achieve "reality" in history, because it puts subjective notions in place of facts and calls these notions reality.
Specialized History, This final type of reflective history focuses on one thread in history, such as "the history of art, of law, or of religion." At the same time, it represents a transitional stage to philosophic history because it takes a "universal viewpoint." The very focus taken (e.g., the history of law) represents a choice on the part of the historian to make a universal concept the guiding rationale for his or her specific history. If the specialized history is good, the author will give an accurate account of the fundamental "Idea" (the "inner guiding soul") that guided the particular events and actions discussed.[6]
Philosophic History, The focus of this third major category of history is the larger process by which Spirit unfolds in the world as history (this is, of course, Hegel's own historical method). Philosophic history prioritizes thought before history, bringing pure philosophical ideas to bear on events. The thoughts that organize the "raw material" of historical events into philosophic history come first and can stand alone--they are a priori. Thus, the philosophic historian studies both the eternal Spirit (which is non-temporal) and the historical process which is its unfolding (a process which is temporal).
The philosophy history as paused by George Frederick Hegel, philosopher and historian and historian has often been viewed as largely technological. It has often been speculated that this philosophical presumption arose from the historical context of Hegel’s life whether negatively from his dedication to the romantic thesis that reason shapes the universe none the less Hegel’s commitment to the dialectical progression of time and to the triumphant end of history is taken to be a largely deterministic and a historical philosophy, such as a reading, I would argue would be a mistaken.
Hegel’s task becomes even more difficult by the question of where to search for his “truth” as philosopher  of history, Hegel concern are primary focused upon the finding basis truths regarding the nature of reality[7]. Because he seeks metaphysical “first principles of nature his results con not judged through outside sources or objective facts, but only through individual reflection and inspiration in contract the philosopher of history is expected to rely almost wholly upon facts and to avoid the contamination of “bias” conclusions about the historical meaning follow not from preconceived no twins but from facts and connection discovered from historical events alone. The chasm separating these two approaches could hardly be more dramatic.
State of nature to be in actual experience answers exactly to the idea of a merely natural conditions freedom as the ideal of that which is original and natural does not exist as original and nature. Rather must it be first sought out and won and that by an in callable medical discipline of the intellectual and moral powers. The state of nature is therefore predominantly that of injustice and violence, of untamed natural impulses fin human deeds and feelings a contrivance for calling the members of the state together for taking the votes and for performing the arithmetical operations of reckoning and comparing the numbers of the state together for taking the voters and for the  different propositions and thereby deeding upon them the state is an abstraction having even its generic existence in its simply generic existence but it is an actuality and its simply generic existence must embody itself  in individual will and activity.[8]
The legal foundation of the state (the constitution) in a constitution the main feature of interest is the self-development of the rational that is the political condition of a people; the setting free of the decisive dements of the idea so that the several powers in the state manifest themselves as separate attain their appropriate and special perfection and yet in this independent condition work together for one object and are held together  from organic whole the state is thus the embodiment of rational freedom, realizing and recognizing itself in an objective form.
The state is the idea of spirit in the external manifestation of human will and its freedom. It is to the state therefore that change in the aspect of history indissolubly attaches itself and the successive phases of the ideal manifest themselves the constitutions under which worked historical political principles the constitutions under which world historical people have reached their collimation are peculiar to them; and therefore do not present a generally application political bios were it otherwise the differences of similar constitutions would consist only in a peculiar method of expanding and developing that generic basis, where as they really originated in diversity of principle.[9]
The mental and moral condition of individuals and their social and religious conditions (the subjective and objective manifestation of reason) exhibit a strict correspondence with each other in every grade of progress they that make them are the like into them” is as true of religious and political ideas as of religious and political idols where man sets no value on that part of his mental and moral life which makes him superior to the brutes, brute life will be an object of worship and bestial sensuality will be the genius of the ritual.
The inward or ideal transition, from Egypt to Greece is as just exhibited but Egypt became a province of the great person kingdom, and the historical transition takes place where the Persian worked comes in contact with the Greek. Here  for the first time an historical transition meet us, vise in the fall of an empire china and idea as already mentioned have remain. Persia has not due transition to Greece is indeed, internal but here it shows itself also externally as a transmission of sovereignty-an occurrence which from this time forward is ever and an on repeated for the Greeks surrender the scepter of dominion and of civilization to the Romans, and the Romans are subdued by the Germans. It we examine this fact of transition more closely the question suggests itself for example, in this first case of the kind, verse Persia why it sank, while china and India remain[10].
It must be observed at the outset, that the phenomenon we investigate-universal history belong to the phenomenon we investigate universal history belongs to the realm of spirit the term “world” includes both physical and physical nature. Physical nature also plays its part in the world’s history and attention will have to be paid to the fundamental natural relations thus involved. But spirit and the course of its development, is our substantial object[11]. Our task does not require us to contemplate nature as a rational system in itself-through in it’s our proper domain it proves itself such but simply in its relation to splint. On the stage on which we are observing it universal history-split displays itself in its most concrete reality. Notwithstanding this (or rather for the very purpose of comprehending the general principles which this, its form of concrete reality, embodies) we must premise some abstract characteristics of the nature of spirit. Such an explanation however cannot be given here under any other farm than that of bare assertion. The present is not the occasion for unfolding the ideal of spirit speculatively, for whatever has a place in an introduction, must as already observed, be taken a simply historical; something assumed as having been explained and proved elsewhere; or whose demonstration awaits the sequel of the science of history itself. We have therefore to mention here. The abstracts characteristics of the nature of spirit and what means spirit uses in order to realize its ideal.
In generally George Frederick Hegel as philosopher and historian as often been viewed as largely ideological he discovered different philosophy in history during the ancient time where by different society for state or become a state due to various factors like state of nature to be in actual also researching about the truth and reality of the nature. Hegel concerns are primary focused upon the finding basic truth regarding the nature of reality has a philosopher  try to investigate about the truth and reality of the nature due to the fact that state from spirit in ward of transition from Egypt to Greece.
       



REFERENCE
Avineri, Shlomo, 1972, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State, Cambridge: Cambridge.
                             University Press. 
Beiser, Frederick C. (ed.), 2008, The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-
                               Century Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brandom, Robert B., 2009, Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas, Cambridge, Mass.:
                                  Harvard University Press.
Bristow, William F. 2007, Hegel and the Transformation of Philosophical Critique, Oxford:
                                   Oxford University Press.
Ferrarin, Alfredo, 2001, Hegel and Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Forster, Michael N., 1989, Hegel and Skepticism, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1976, Hegel's Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, P. Christopher  
                                     Smith (trans.), New Haven: Yale University Press. 
http://www.historicalinsights.com/dave/hegel.html accessed on Sunday at 02:20 pm   (2015 )

FREE THINKER,
DAMIAN GABINUS,
dgabinus.blogspot.com,
dgabinus@gmail.com
+255767271987
TANZANIA-MBEYA CITY.


No comments:

Post a Comment